Introduction: The Relational Self: Basic Forms of Self-Awareness
- Published: 20 January 2020
- Volume 39 , pages 501–507, ( 2020 )
Cite this article
- Anna Ciaunica 1
8188 Accesses
2 Citations
35 Altmetric
Explore all metrics
Avoid common mistakes on your manuscript.
Self-awareness, the feeling that our experiences are bound to the self—as a unitary entity distinct from others and the rest of the world—is a key aspect of the human mind. But how do we become aware of ourselves in a constantly changing and complex physical and social environment? How do we relate to others while keeping in touch with one’s self, with the fundamental feeling that there is an ‘I’ at the core of all our experiences and exchanges with the world and others? How is it possible to navigate such a dynamic environment without losing track of one’s self? What are the mechanisms underlying typical and atypical self-awareness and how can we spell them out within a coherent conceptual and empirical framework? What are the most basic or minimal forms of self-awareness? Is the minimal self relational or is it preferable to conceptualise it in an individualistic manner, as a fundamentally subjective sense of mineness? Is there is a ‘sense of we’, and if yes, what is its relationship with the minimal ‘individualistic’ self?
This special issue tackles these key questions by bringing together papers from philosophy, developmental and clinical psychology and theoretical neuroscience. The aim is to provide a multifaceted, interdisciplinary and rich perspective on the perennial and fundamental questions i) “what is a (minimal) self?” and ii) “how the self relates to the world and others?”
The papers in this special issue can be divided into three main groups. The first consists of four papers discussing the question whether (i) the minimal self is best understood and defined relationally, that is in terms of social interactions; or rather (ii) the minimal self is a tacit, non-socially grounded, experiential self-awareness. The second group contains three papers and combines resources from theoretical neuroscience (the Predictive Processing framework), experimental work (developmental studies), and philosophy in order to emphasise the fundamentally dynamic aspect of self-awareness. Finally, the last group consists in three papers bringing insights into these questions by focusing on atypical forms of self-awareness and social interactions, in particular schizophrenia and Autism Spectrum Condition. In what follows I provide a brief synopsis each of these contributions.
1 Minimal and Relational Self: Conceptual Issues
Hutto and Ilundáin‐Agurruza ’s “Selfless activity and experience: radicalizing minimal self-awareness” begins the special issue by offering a rich discussion of the key question “how best to characterize the most fundamental ways social creatures have of engaging and sharing experiences with others?”. They contrast relational and non-relational or individualistic views of the self. For example, relationalists hold that whatever awareness of the self exactly involves it is acquired through interactions with others. By contrast, the rival non-relationalist view of selfhood, individualists for short, assume that we possess a tacit sense or awareness of the self—a kind of non-socially grounded self- awareness—that is either already implicated in the way we act successfully in the world and in the ways that we experience the world and our actions in phenomenally charged ways. Pivotally, however, if such deflationary individualist theories of the self are accepted, then pre-reflexive self-awareness is at least one primitive, defining feature of who we are that would need to be in place before we are in a position to relate to and intersubjectively engage with others. They attempt to “give the individualists their due”, explicating how we might positively understand the distinctive, nonconceptual experience of our own actions and experiences, by drawing on insights from a radically enactive take on phenomenal experience. They also defend a late-developing relationalism about the emergence of explicit, conceptually based self-awareness, proposing that the latter develops in tandem with the mastery of self-reflective narrative practices. In doing so, they challenge Ciaunica’s ( 2017 ) developmental relationism which defends the possibility that there are quite basic forms of skin-to-skin sharing with others that precede rather than presuppose the exercise of empathetic abilities. They argue that our first conceptual, explicit sense of self is something that only arrives on the scene once we become able to hold our own—through the support of others—in discursive, narrative practices that give us a conceptual grip on what it is to be a temporally extended self that persists.
Bolis and Schilbach ’s “ ‘I interact therefore I am’: the self as a historical product of dialectical attunement” proposes a shift in perspective, i.e. moving from addressing the question of self-awareness from ‘being’ to ‘becoming’. They hold the radical claim that we construe the ‘self’ as a dynamic process rather than as a static entity. To this end they draw on dialectics and Bayesian accounts of cognition which allows us to holistically consider the ‘self’ as the interplay between internalization and externalization and the latter to operationalize our suggestion formally. Internalization is considered here as the co-construction of bodily hierarchical models of the (social) world and the organism, while externalization is taken as the collective transformation of the world. They suggest that the self is an historical product of dialectical attunement across multiple time scales, from species evolution and culture to individual development and everyday learning. Specifically, they describe concrete means for empirically testing their proposal in the form of two-person psychophysiology and multi-level analyses of intersubjectivity. In short, they argue that a fine-grained analysis of social interaction might allow us to reconsider the ‘self’ beyond the static individual, i.e. how it emerges and manifests itself in social relations. They make the case that such an approach could be relevant in multiple fields, from ethics and psychiatry to pedagogy and artificial intelligence.
Higgings ’s “The ‘we’ in ‘me’: an account of minimal relational selfhood” critically discusses the idea that selfhood involves a uniquely first-personal experiential dimension, which precedes any form of socially dependent selfhood (Gallagher 2005 ; Legrand 2007 ; Strawson 2009 ; Kriegel 2009 ; Nida-Rümelin 2017 ; Zahavi 1999 , 2011 , 2014 , 2016 , 2017a , b ). In his paper he draws attention against the temptation to view minimal experiential selfhood as “ontogenetically more primitive” (Zahavi 2014 , p. 14) than socially constituted selfhood. In other words, he argues that the ‘thinnest’ construal of minimal experiential selfhood fails to properly account for characteristics that are essential to human selfhood; namely, the intimate, embodied interactions that unfold at the incipient moments of human life. He argues that taking the ontogenesis of embodied human existence seriously involves accepting the de facto equiprimordiality of minimal experientialism with a ‘minimal’ form of relational selfhood, i.e. the co-constitution of experience through engagements with others. Specifically, he focuses on the dynamical and relational structure of consciousness, as a property of human beings considered holistically (i.e. as embodied beings) who are embedded in subject- dependent contexts and are therefore irreducible to descriptions that accord with some independent ‘objective’. In doing so he draws on work by Krueger ( 2013 , 2015 ) to show that early stages of human life, inclusive of the perspective of phenomenal consciousness, involve shared experiential states, in which one’s experiences are constitutively dependent on the modulatory role of others. One’s corporeality is thereby partly given over to another’s agency. Lastly, these kinds of experiential states are shown to be present at the most incipient moments of human life, thereby affirming that any naturalistically grounded notion of pre- reflective human minimal selfhood should be construed as ontogenetically equiprimordial with socially constituted experience. Such socially constituted experience amounts to a form of minimal relational selfhood, which is not preceded by any other dimension of selfhood within the manifestation of human life.
Leon ’s “For-me-ness, for-us-ness, and the we-relationship” investigates the relationship between for-me-ness and sociality. He draws very careful conceptual distinctions in order to point out some ambiguities in claims pursued by some of the critics that have recently pressed on the relationship between the two notions. He starts with the observation that the idea of for-me-ness or mineness raises a host of far-reaching questions, some of which concern its proper characterization, pervasiveness, phenomenal reality, and its relation to the prospects of providing a naturalistic account of consciousness. Leon notices that the proposal according to which there is a very tight link between subjectivity and sociality is certainly not new in the philosophical and psychological literature. However, a novel feature of some of the recent criticisms to the received understanding of for-me-ness is that they don’t appeal to language, narratives, social roles or cultural context to support this view, but rather to bottom-up approaches from developmental psychology (Ciaunica and Fotopoulou 2017 ; Ciaunica 2016 ). The main aim of his contribution is to discuss the relationship between for-me-ness and sociality, mainly in the context of recent criticisms to the received understanding of for-me-ness that have appealed to research in developmental psychology. He articulates a question concerning this relationship that builds on the idea that, occasionally at least, there is something it is like ‘for us’ to have an experience. This idea, he argues, has been explored in recent literature on shared experiences and collective intentionality (Schmid 2014a , b ), and it gestures towards the question of the extent to which some social interactions make a difference in the phenomenal character of their participants’ experiences. In the main part of his article, Leon proposes a construal of for-us-ness that complements the received understanding of for-me-ness, by drawing on Alfred Schutz’ concept of the “we-relationship” (Schutz 1962 , 1967 ; Schutz and Luckmann 1973 ), and on the idea of second-personal awareness, i.e. awareness of a ‘you’, as distinguished from awareness of a ‘she’ or he’. He concludes that this proposal provides a suitable account of basic forms of phenomenally manifest social connectedness, in a way that is cognitively undemanding and without incurring the theoretical costs of positing a sui generis plural pre-reflective self-awareness (Schmid 2014a ).
2 The Dynamic, Situated and Scaffolded Self
Kiverstein ’s “Free energy and the self: an ecological-enactive interpretation” addresses the interesting question: how did the feeling of being alive get started? One key observation is that not all living things feel alive. Plants almost certainly don’t. Bacteria are capable of a minimal form of purposive agency (Fulda 2017 ; Di Paolo et al 2017 ). However, since they lack a brain for regulating the changing internal state of their bodies, they probably also lack feeling (Thompson 2015 ). But what about insects that continue behaving in the same way when they have suffered severe injuries? They too most likely lack feeling insofar as their behaviour seems to be unaffected by damage to their bodies. Kiverstein give us an account about how subjectivity might have emerged early in evolutionary history out of processes of action control. In other words, subjectivity might be thought of as tied to processes of purposive agency on the one hand, and sensorimotor integration on the other. He defends the “phenomenological theory of selfhood” according to which any naturalistic explanation of phenomenal consciousness in the terms of psychology and the neurosciences will need to explain how mineness can be intrinsic to phenomenal consciousness. He gives a detailed account of a such naturalistic explanation that takes selfhood to emerge out of self-organising biological processes.
Kiverstein builds upon the free energy principle, according to which any living system will aim to minimise free energy in its sensory exchanges with the environment (Friston 2007 ). He shows how such a process of free energy minimisation is accomplished through a process referred to as “active inference”. He claims that active inference is best understood in ecological and enactive terms, with focus on the coupled dynamics of the animal in its eco-niche that lead towards dynamic equilibrium (Bruineberg and Rietveld 2014 ; Bruineberg et al. 2017 ). Importantly, active inference doesn’t suffice to explain mineness, since every living system will keep its own free energy to a minimum through a process of active inference. In order to address this key question, Kiverstein asks: what would need to be added to active inference to yield mineness? He suggests that recent theoretical work by Karl Friston may give us an answer to this question (Friston 2018 ). The basic idea is that once an organism reaches the level of complexity so that it can act to minimise its own expected free energy, mineness will emerge as intrinsic to the process of life itself. The author closes his paper by showing how the resulting account of mineness supports a relational theory of the self. This is because on this ecological and enactive reading of active inference the organism and its environment are co-specifying, and co-determining. The argument of Kiverstein’s paper is that any organism capable of action control of the right complexity will also be a self. Since organisms are best understood in relation to their environment, so also are selves.
Crucianelli and Filippetti ’s “Developmental perspectives on interpersonal affective touch” draws attention to a relatively overlooked aspect of interpersonal affective touch in shaping self-awareness and body ownership from the outset, in early life. They start with the basic observation that our first sensorial experiences, which provide us with information about our own body and the surrounding environment arise in the womb (Ciaunica 2016 , 2017 ; Ciaunica & Crucianelli 2019 ). In these early sensory interactions, touch is possibly the first route by which the developing body receives inputs from the external world and gradually shapes one’s body boundaries and its capabilities for action (e.g. Atkinson and Braddick 1982 ; Bernhardt 1987 ; Bremner and Lewkowicz 2012 ). The skin is the largest of our sensory organs and wraps our entire body surface (Serino and Haggard 2010 ; Gallace and Spence 2014 ); hence, evidence suggests that touch might play a pivotal role in developing a sense of self as separate from the other (see Field 2010 for a review). Somewhat paradoxically, touch is also our most social sense since it is fundamentally involved in how we explore the environment and engage in successful interactions (Gallace 2012 ; Ebisch et al. 2014 ; Rochat 2011 ; Gallace and Spence 2014 ), as well as how we bond with other people and form interpersonal attachments. In their paper they review and discuss recent developmental and adult findings, pointing to the central role of interpersonal affective touch in body awareness and social cognition in health and disorders. They propose that interpersonal affective touch, as an interoceptive modality invested of a social nature, can uniquely contribute to the ongoing debate in philosophy about the primacy of the relational nature of the minimal self. In the wake of these recent conceptualisations, Crucianelli and Filippetti review experimental and clinical evidence supporting the importance of interpersonal affective touch to the way we recognise and make sense of our body as our own. In line with previous work by Ciaunica ( 2017 ) and Ciaunica & Fotopoulou ( 2017 ) they defend the claim that affective touch constitutes a fundamental aspect of bodily self-consciousness (Blanke 2012 ; Dijkerman 2015 ) from the very first stages of human life.
Gallotti ’s “Shared and social discourse” discusses the scope and importance of claims about shared intentionality in social discourse. What is it for the capacity of sharing mental attitudes and contents to play an explanatory role in the study of the social mind? The motivation for addressing this question is originally tied to theoretical preoccupations about the tendency to make claims about shared and, especially, ‘we- intentionality’ in support of arguments about socially extended forms of mentality. The fact that evidence is interpreted as showing that shared intentionality works as a scaffolding for the development of full- blown, representational and normative, thinking, is often associated with claims about the conditions for the existence and identity of mental attitudes and contents being social all the way down. This argumentative line is present in several strands of social-cognitive research at the intersection of studies of shared intentionality and radically (i.e. en-active) externalist views of the mind, but it has not yet been articulated in a satisfactory manner. The key question is what human cognition could be like on the premise that humans are capable of creating cultures and institutions of unique complexity in the animal kingdom. Tomasello’s response is an account of the evolution of the human mind, which identifies the origin of species-specific forms of modern thinking in the emergence of a genetically evolved psychological adaptation for engaging in cognitively shared activities with co-specifics (Tomasello and Carpenter 2007 ; Call 2009 ). In a similar vein, Jane Heal has offered an authoritative formulation of the significance of shared cognitive activities in philosophical work on co-cognition (Heal 2013 ). Building upon earlier reflections on co-cognition in simulation theory (Heal 1998 ), Heal draws on insights about shared intentionality to advocate ‘Co-cognitivism’, the view that the logical structure and criteria of adequacy of psychological concepts are determined with a view to the sort of activities that individuals pursue together in everyday life. Co-cognitivism and the ‘Shared Intentionality Hypothesis' gesture to something like a general view of the function of shared intentionality, which has only begun to emerge in the philosophy of mind and society. The idea is that human psychology has evolved in accordance with the fact that novel routes to knowledge of things become available to interacting agents when they align their mental and bodily resources and act as a ‘we’ (Tollefsen and Dale 2012 ; Gallotti et al. 2017 ). Gallotti's goal is to develop a more balanced, if not cautious, assessment of the explanatory role of claims about shared intentionality in social discourse.
3 Minimal and Relational Self and its Disruptions
Krueger ’s “Schizophrenia and the scaffolded self” takes as a starting point a family of recent externalist approaches in philosophy of mind which argue that our psychological capacities are synchronically and diachronically “scaffolded” by external (i.e., beyond-the-brain) resources. Surprisingly, he writes, despite much recent interest in this topic, it has not yet found its way to philosophy of psychiatry in a substantive way. Since disturbances of affectivity figure so prominently in a wide variety of mental disorders, the topic seems like a fruitful place to bridge externalist paradigms and psychiatry. The main aim of his paper is an attempt to build such a bridge. Krueger considers how these “scaffolded” approaches might inform debates in phenomenological psychopathology. In doing so, he first introduces the idea of “affective scaffolding” and makes some taxonomic distinctions. More specifically, he uses schizophrenia as a case study to argue—along with others in phenomenological psychopathology—that schizophrenia is fundamentally a self- disturbance. Building upon previous existing work, he offers a subtle reconfiguration of these approaches. He claims that schizophrenia is not simply a disruption of ipseity or minimal self-consciousness but rather a disruption of the scaffolded self, established and regulated via its ongoing engagement with the world and others. He concludes that this way of thinking about the scaffolded self is potentially transformative both for our theoretical as well as practical understanding of the causes and character of schizophrenic experience, insofar as it suggests the need to consider new forms of intervention and treatment.
Constant , Bervoets , Hens and Van de Cruys ’s “Precise worlds for certain minds: An ecological perspective on the relational self in autism” addresses the question of how the various aspects of the relational self are experienced by people presented with clear challenges in social interaction, such as people with Autism Spectrum Condition (ASC). Indeed, relational and social accounts of the self posit that the sense of self depends on the entanglement of the individual with a significant, or generalized other, understood respectively as the representation of an individual profound significance in one’s life (Andersen and Chen 2002 ), and as the individually internalized ‘attitude of a whole community’ (Mead 1934 ). On that view, the self would heavily rest on the individual’s ability to coordinate a diversified repertoire of selves (cf. Zahavi 2010 ) accumulated over time through interpersonal relationships (Andersen and Chen 2002 ). However, ASC offers an interesting challenge for the relational views of the self precisely because it is broadly recognized as a disorder primarily impacting social relationships. Indeed, while they do not claim that autistic people completely lack a sense of self, many influential theories tend to suggest that the requirements for a sense of relational self are reduced or otherwise impaired. Yet, the abundance of autobiographical reports (Van Goidsenhoven and Masschelein 2016 ) by autistic people across the spectrum suggests that a desire for self-identification and recognition is particularly pronounced in people with ASC. Building upon the influential predictive processing (PP) paradigm, in explaining core behavioral traits of ASC (e.g., Lawson et al. 2014 ; Palmer et al. 2015 ; Pellicano and Burr 2012 ; Van de Cruys et al. 2014 ) PP approaches challenge the claims about the presence of specific neurocognitive dysfunctions in autistic cognition, as it traces back the symptoms of ASC to normal, though differently ‘tuned’, domain general neurocognitive mechanisms (cf. Bolis and Schilbach 2017 ).
The main aim of their paper is to use the PP paradigm to attempt an ecological explanation of atypicalities of the relational self in ASC, specifically, those relating to its minimal, extended, and intersubjective aspects, though without positing major incapacities in social functioning. The main focus is in how these aspects become organized in patterns of sensory and social interactions with the body (e.g., interoception), the world (e.g., exteroception and material (environment), and other agents (e.g., social interactions). Specifically, they focus on a recent PP account of ASC called “HIPPEA”, the High, Inflexible Precision of Prediction Errors in Autism account (Van de Cruys et al. 2014 ). PP accounts of ASC emphasize different aspects of PP, even though they generally include a treatment of all basic mechanisms. The focus on HIPPEA is motivated by its interpretation of the mechanism of meta-learning. According to PP, meta-learning enables to detect learnable sensory cues, relevant for predicting future events with a certain level of reliability. It is a mechanism crucial to distinguish random sensory variability from the variability reporting causal regularities (e.g., recurrent causes of inputs). This new account enables a leverage the ecological and embodied implications of PP to discuss aspects of the relational self in ASC. The ecological implications of PP for understanding ASC are far-reaching (e.g., Bolis and Schilbach 2017 ; von der Lühe et al. 2016 ), but have so far not been exhaustively treated in the literature. This paper intends to fill this gap.
Kartner and Clowes ’s “The pre-reflective situational self” critically addresses the idea that pre-reflective self-awareness constitutes a minimal self. They argue that there are reasons to doubt this constituting role of mineness. Specifically, they claim that there are alternative possibilities and that the necessity for an adequate theory of the self within psychopathology gives us good reasons to believe that we need a thicker notion of the pre-reflective self. The authors propose instead the idea of a Pre-Reflective Situational Self. In a first step, they show how alternative conceptions of pre-reflective self-awareness point to philosophical problems with the standard phenomenological view. They claim that this is mainly due to fact that within the phenomenological account the mineness aspect is implicitly playing several roles. Consequently, they argue that a thin interpretation of pre-reflective self-awareness—based on a thin notion of mineness—cannot do its needed job within psychopathology. Rather a thicker conception of pre-reflective self is needed. In their proposal they carefully develop the notion of a pre-reflective situational self by analyzing the dynamical nature of the relation between self-awareness and the world, specifically through our interactive inhabitation of the social world. Specifically they discuss three alternative views which give reasons to question the standard phenomenological interpretation of pre-reflective self- awareness. They start by reviewing several of the most important of these, namely the cognitive view, the structure-awareness view and the relational view and show that each cast rather different light upon the interrelations between first-person givenness, mineness and the minimal self. They argue that the problematic nature of pre-reflective self-awareness this is especially revealed in the context of the Ipseity Hypothesis of Schizophrenia. Here, the thin notion of pre-reflective self does not appear to do what is required of it, namely to fulfil the necessary conceptual role in explaining what appears disrupted in this type of mental illness. This is problematic in their view, as the deployment of the notion of minimal self in “ipseity theories” of schizophrenia might be thought to be one place where the notion of pre-reflective self-awareness earns its status as a concept that has some empirical standing (Nordgaard and Parnas 2014 ; Parnas et al. 2005 ; Sass et al. 2013 ) In their paper they use this discussion to link it to related work on self-diminishment in schizophrenia, namely the self-diminishment view (Lysaker and Lysaker 2008 ) in order to argue that our sense of pre-reflective self is better understood as labile and situational through a thicker conception of self than is entertained in the more standard phenomenological views. On these grounds, they conclude that our sense of pre-reflective self in part must be dynamical in order to reflect our fluid embedding in shifting social contexts.
Andersen SM, Chen S (2002) The relational self: an interpersonal social-cognitive theory. Psychol Rev 109(4):619–645
Article Google Scholar
Atkinson J, Braddick O (1982) Sensory and perceptual capacities of the neonate. In: Stratton P (ed) Psychobiology of the human newborn. Wiley, London, pp 191–220
Google Scholar
Bernhardt J (1987) Sensory capabilities of the fetus. MCN Am J Matern Child Nurs 12(1):44–47
Blanke O (2012) Multisensory brain mechanisms of bodily selfconsciousness. Nat Rev Neurosci 13(8):556
Bolis D, Schilbach L (2017) Observing and participating in social interactions: action perception and action control across the autistic spectrum. Dev Cogn Neurosci 29:168–175
Bremner AJ, Lewkowicz DJ, Spence C (2012) The multisensory approach to development. In: Bremner AJ, Lewkowicz DJ, Spence C (eds) Multisensory development. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–26
Chapter Google Scholar
Bruineberg J, Rietveld E (2014) Self-organisation, free energy minimisation, and optimal grip on a field of affordances. Front Human Neurosci 8:599
Bruineberg J, Kiverstein J, Rietveld E (2017) The anticipating brain is not a scientist: the free energy principle from an ecological-enactive perspective. Synthese 195:2417–2444
Call J (2009) Contrasting the social cognition of humans and nonhuman apes: the shared intentionality hypothesis. Topics Cogn Sci 1:368–379
Ciaunica A (2016) Basic forms of pre-reflective self-consciousness: a developmental perspective. In: Miguens S, Preyer G, Bravo Morando C (eds) Pre-reflective consciousness: sartre and contemporary philosophy of mind. Routledge, London
Ciaunica A (2017) The meeting of bodies: basic forms of shared experiences. Topoi, Int J Philos. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-017-9500-x
Ciaunica A, Crucianelli L (2019) Minimal self-consciousness from within – a developmental perspective. J Conscious Stud 26(3–4):207–226
Ciaunica A, Fotopoulou A (2017) The touched self: psychological and philosophical perspectives on proximal intersubjectivity and the self. In: Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes C (eds) Embodiment, enaction, and culture: investigating the constitution of the shared world. MIT Press, Cambridge.
Craig AD (2002) Opinion: how do you feel? Interoception: the sense of the physiological condition of the body. Nat Rev Neurosci 3(8):655
Craig AD, Craig AD (2009) How do you feel–now? The anterior insula and human awareness. Nat Rev Neurosci 10(1):59–70
Di Paolo E, Buhrmann T, Barandiaran XE (2017) Sensorimotor life: an enactive proposal. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Book Google Scholar
Dijkerman HC (2015) How do different aspects of self-consciousness interact? Trends Cogn Sci 19(8):427–428
Ebisch SJ, Ferri F, Gallese V (2014) Touching moments: desire modulates the neural anticipation of active romantic caress. Front Behav Neurosci 8:60
Field T (2010) Touch for socioemotional and physical well-being: a review. Dev Rev 30(4):367–383
Friston K (2007) Free energy and the brain. Synthese 159(3):417–458
Friston K (2018) (ms) Am I self-conscious. Manuscript under review, frontiers in theoretical and philosophical psychology philosophical and ethical aspects of a science of consciousness and the self
Fulda FC (2017) Natural agency: the case of bacterial cognition. J Am Philos Assoc 3:1–22
Gallace A (2012) Living with touch. Psychologist 25(12):896–899
Gallace A, Spence C (2014) In touch with the future: the sense of touch from cognitive neuroscience to virtual reality. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Gallagher S (2005) How the body shapes the mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Gallotti M, Fairhurst MT, Frith CD (2017) ‘Alignment in social interactions’. Conscious Cogn 48:253–261
Heal J (1998) Co-cognition and off-line simulation: two ways of understanding the simulation approach. Mind Lang 13:477–498
Heal J (2013) Social anti-individualism, co-cognitivism and second-person authority. Mind 122:340–371
Kriegel U (2009) Subjective consciousness: a self-representational theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Krueger J (2013) Merleau-ponty on shared emotions and the joint ownership thesis. Cont Philos Rev 46(4):509–531
Krueger J (2015) The affective 'we': self-regulation and shared emotions. In: Szanto T, Moran D (eds) The phenomenology of sociality: discovering the 'We'. Routledge, New York, pp 263–280
Lawson RP, Rees G, Friston KJ (2014) An aberrant precision account of autism. Front Hum Neurosci 8:302
Legrand D (2007) Pre-reflective self-as-subject from experiential and empirical perspectives. Conscious Cogn 16(3):583–599
Lysaker PH, Lysaker JT (2008) Schizophrenia and the fate of the self. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Mead HG (1934) Mind, self, and society. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Nida-Rümelin M (2017) Self-awareness. Rev Philos Psychol 8(1):55–82
Nordgaard J, Parnas J (2014) Self-disorders and the schizophrenia spectrum: a study of 100 first hospital admissions. Schizophr Bull 40(6):1300–1307
Palmer CJ, Paton B, Enticott PG, Hohwy J (2015) “Subtypes” in the presentation of autistic traits in the general adult population. J Autism Dev Disord 45(5):1291–1301
Parnas J, Møller P, Kircher T, Thalbitzer J, Jansson L, Handest P, Zahavi D (2005) EASE: examination of anomalous self-experience. Psychopathology 38(5):236–258
Pellicano E, Burr D (2012) When the world becomes “too real”: a Bayesian explanation of autistic perception. Trends Cogn Sci 16(10):504–510
Rochat P (2011) Possession and morality in early development. New Dir Child Adolesc Dev 2011(132):23–38
Sass LA, Pienkos E, Nelson B, Medford N (2013) Anomalous self-experience in depersonalization and schizophrenia: a comparative investigation. Conscious Cogn 22(2):430–441
Schmid HB (2014a) Plural self-awareness. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 13(1):7–24
Schmid HB (2014b) The feeling of being a group. Corporate emotions and collective consciousness. In: von Scheve C, Salmela M (eds) Collective emotions: perspectives from psychology, philosophy, and sociology. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Schutz A (1962) Collected papers I the problem of social reality. M. Nijhoff, Hague
Schutz A (1967) Phenomenology of the social world. Northwestern University Press, Evanston
Schutz A, Luckmann T (1973) The structures of the life-world (Vol. I). Northwestern University Press, Evanston
Serino A, Haggard P (2010) Touch and the body. Neurosci Biobehav Rev 34(2):224–236
Strawson G (2009) Selves: an essay in revisionary metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Thompson E (2015) Waking, dreaming, being: self and consciousness in neuroscience, meditation and philosophy. Columbia University Press, New York
Tollefsen D, Dale R (2012) Naturalizing joint action: a process-based approach. Philos Psychol 25:385–407
Tomasello M, Carpenter M (2007) Shared intentionality. Dev Sci 10:121–125
Van de Cruys S, Evers K, Van der Hallen R, Van Eylen L, Boets B, de-Wit L, Wagemans J (2014) Precise minds in uncertain worlds: predictive coding in autism. Psychol Rev 121(4):649–675
Van Goidsenhoven L, Masschelein A (2016) Donna Williams’s “triumph”: looking for “the place in the middle”at jessica kingsley publishers. Life Writ 2016:1–23
von der Lühe T, Manera V, Barisic I, Becchio C, Vogeley K, Schilbach L (2016) Interpersonal predictive coding, not action perception, is impaired in autism. Philos Trans R Soc Lond Ser B Biol Sci 371:20150373
Zahavi D (1999) Self-awareness and alterity: a phenomenological investigation. Northwestern University Press, Chicago
Zahavi D (2005) Subjectivity and selfhood: investigating the first-person perspective. MIT Press, Cambridge
Zahavi D (2010) Complexities of self. Autism 14(5):547–551
Zahavi D (2011) The experiential self: objections and clarifications. In: Sidertis M, Thompson E, Zahavi D (eds) Self, no self? Perspectives from analytical, phenomenological, and indian traditions. Oxford University Press, Oxford, p 5678
Zahavi D (2014) Self & other: exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zahavi D (2016) Openness versus interdependence: a reply to Kyselo. Philos Psychol 29(7):1066–1067
Zahavi D (2017a) Thin, thinner, thinnest: defining the minimal self. In: Durt C, Fuchs T, Tewes C (eds) Embodiment, enaction, and culture: investigating the constitution of the shared world. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 193–200
Zahavi D (2017b) ‘Consciousness and (minimal) selfhood: getting clearer on for-me-ness and mineness’. In: Kriegel U (ed.) The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Download references
Author information
Authors and affiliations.
Senior Researcher Institute of Philosophy Porto, Portugal & Research Associate Institute of Cognitive Neuroscience, UCL, London, UK
Anna Ciaunica
You can also search for this author in PubMed Google Scholar
Corresponding author
Correspondence to Anna Ciaunica .
Additional information
Publisher's note.
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Rights and permissions
Reprints and permissions
About this article
Ciaunica, A. Introduction: The Relational Self: Basic Forms of Self-Awareness. Topoi 39 , 501–507 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-020-09689-z
Download citation
Published : 20 January 2020
Issue Date : July 2020
DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-020-09689-z
Share this article
Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:
Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.
Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative
- Find a journal
- Publish with us
- Track your research
An official website of the United States government
Official websites use .gov A .gov website belongs to an official government organization in the United States.
Secure .gov websites use HTTPS A lock ( Lock Locked padlock icon ) or https:// means you've safely connected to the .gov website. Share sensitive information only on official, secure websites.
- Publications
- Account settings
- Advanced Search
- Journal List
The Mindful Self: A Mindfulness-Enlightened Self-view
Qianguo xiao, caizhen yue, jia-yuan yu.
- Author information
- Article notes
- Copyright and License information
Edited by: Katja Corcoran, University of Graz, Austria
Reviewed by: Dominik Mischkowski, National Institutes of Health (NIH), United States; Tomasz Jankowski, The John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin, Poland
*Correspondence: Jia-yuan Yu, [email protected]
This article was submitted to Personality and Social Psychology, a section of the journal Frontiers in Psychology
Received 2016 Oct 18; Accepted 2017 Sep 22; Collection date 2017.
This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (CC BY). The use, distribution or reproduction in other forums is permitted, provided the original author(s) or licensor are credited and that the original publication in this journal is cited, in accordance with accepted academic practice. No use, distribution or reproduction is permitted which does not comply with these terms.
This paper analyzes studies of mindfulness and the self, with the aim of deepening our understanding of the potential benefits of mindfulness and meditation for mental health and well-being. Our review of empirical research reveals that positive changes in attitudes toward the self and others as a result of mindfulness-enabled practices can play an important role in modulating many mental and physical health problems. Accordingly, we introduce a new concept—the “mindful self”—and compare it with related psychological constructs to describe the positive changes in self-attitude associated with mindfulness meditation practices or interventions. The mindful self is conceptualized as a mindfulness-enlightened self-view and attitude developed by internalizing and integrating the essence of Buddhist psychology into one’s self-system. We further posit that the mindful self will be an important intermediary between mindfulness intervention and mental health problems, and an important moderator in promoting well-being. More generally, we suggest that the mindful self may also be an applicable concept with which to describe and predict the higher level of self-development of those who grow up in the culture of Buddhism or regularly engage in meditation over a long period of time.
Keywords: mindfulness, self, self-development, self-view, self-attitude, Buddhist psychology
Introduction
Buddhist psychology is largely focused on analyzing and understanding the nature of the self, and many positive effects of meditative practice based on Buddhist psychology have been documented by researchers interested in self-processes ( Gallagher and Shear, 1999 ). The central tenet of Buddhist psychology with respect to the self is that of “no self,” which posits that there is no unchangeable self. This differs from some schools of Western psychology in considering the concept of the self, though in some descriptions there are many similarities ( McIntosh, 1997 ). In modern Western psychology, the self is constructed as a definable knowable entity with particular characteristics, universal needs, and somewhat predictable developmental thrusts ( Sedikides and Spencer, 2007 ; Chan, 2008 ; Donner, 2010 ). For most people, the self refers to the things immediately connected to their body, and more importantly to their mind. It seems self-evident that perceptually, “I am the mind and the mind is I” ( Chan, 2008 ). Social-cognitive approaches to the self, as well as clinical practice, teach people that it is important to expend much energy solidifying and bolstering their sense of self, (re)-establishing secure attachments, as well as promoting self-esteem. However, Buddhist teachings maintain that the self is an illusion that is truly the cause of much of our suffering. Thus, according to Buddhism, people should let go of as many attachments as possible, which are very difficult to give up in actuality. As a result, there appears to be a fundamental paradox in current clinical practice. It is undeniably important to develop continuity, identity, and an ongoing sense of self for all who suffer from pathological disturbances in their subjective sense of selfhood; yet, under Buddhist psychology, it is equally clear that adhering to a sense of personal continuity and self-identity results in chronic discontent and psychic conflict ( Engler, 1984 ; Rubin, 2013 ). In effect, neither theoretical position should be favored over the other: overemphasizing the approach of Buddhist psychology may bring about an impairment of an individual’s self-conception, while focusing disproportionately on self-entity could lead to the formation and fantasy of self-stability ( Rubin, 1996 ). A cogent theory of self should take into consideration aspects from both of these two standpoints, helping individuals to be more flexible ( Falkenström, 2003 ).
Over the past two decades, an increasing number of researchers in the West have recognized that Buddhist doctrines (especially those concerning meditation practice), as well as the Chan (Zen) form of Chinese Buddhism, offer profound observations and effective methods with which to enlighten the experiencing self ( Falkenström, 2003 ). Numerous studies have suggested, for example, that mindfulness meditation offers significant positive effects in reducing various physical and mental symptoms, enhancing self-functioning ( Rigby et al., 2014 ), facilitating self-integration ( Rubin, 2013 ), and altering the perspective of self-observation ( Shapiro et al., 2006 ). The present study further contends that, consistent with the traditional aims of meditation in Eastern cultures, where it has been practiced for 1000s of years, the principal cause or mechanism underlying all these positive changes of self attained through Western scientific mindfulness practice or intervention is the reconstruction of a mindful self-view and attitude. In other words, we argue that positive changes such as these result from the integration and internalization of the mindful or meditative self-view and attitude which encompass notions of the non-self, impermanence, non-attachment, and equanimity. Therefore, we propose a new concept—the “mindful self”—to describe the mindfulness-enlightened self-view and attitude as these are explored in the present study. The paper describes the connotations of this concept and its psychological functioning as a new self-construct in the context of adult self-development.
Mindfulness in Buddhism and Psychology
Buddhist psychology is an in-depth examination of the self that aims to lead humans to a flourishing life, while mindfulness meditation is a central factor in helping one to live such a life ( Edge, 2014 ). Buddhist psychology affirms that there is no such thing as a permanent, unchanging self ( Olendzki, 2010 ), and further contends that suffering pervades human existence and is chiefly caused by one’s greed, hatred, and delusion concerning what is felt and seen, as well as an illusory belief in the notion that there is an independent, permanent self. According to the Buddha, the only way to eradicate human anguish or suffering is to remove the attachment ( upadana ) or craving ( trsna ) of our mind toward various things or concepts to which we are attached. Mindfulness meditation is one of the most important elements of the Buddha’s “noble eightfold path” to end suffering and instill wisdom. Principally, mindfulness in Buddhist teaching is viewed as a fundamental pathway through which to become aware of the causes and sources of suffering and to attain enlightenment or an awakening, thereby enabling the individual to be less egoistical and obtain insight into the state of “no self.” According to Buddhism and its Chan School, when an individual has truly acquired complete enlightenment or insight into the “non-self,” they will have achieved full freedom of the mind.
The Buddhist concept “ sati ” was first translated as “mindfulness” from the Pali word by a British scholar of the language, Thomas William Rhys Davids, in 1881, based on his understanding of the Mahasatipatthana Sutta , which stresses how its practice is to watch how things “come to be” and how they “pass away” ( Gethin, 2011 ). “Mindfulness meditation” has been studied extensively over the past two decades in the West, and is understood either as a process of self-observation (e.g., Martin, 1997 ), as a set of skills for self-regulation (e.g., Hayes and Wilson, 2003 ), or as a disposition or kind of cognitive ability (e.g., Kudesia and Nyima, 2014 ). Although there is some confusion regarding the differing definitions of mindfulness in terms of awareness, attention, and attitude ( Harrington and Pickles, 2009 ; Mikulas, 2011 ), a widely adopted description is that it is a particular way of paying attention, a process of non-judgmental awareness ( Goldstein, 2002 ; Bishop et al., 2004 ; Kabat-Zinn, 2005 ; Kabat-Zinn and Hanh, 2009 ), and an attitude of openness and acceptance ( Shapiro et al., 2006 ). As an essential agent of a functioning mindfulness, mindfulness meditation is a way of looking deeply into oneself in a spirit of self-inquiry and self-understanding ( Kabat-Zinn and Hanh, 2009 ) by a process of dis-identification or decentering with respect to the contents of the mind, and an experiential movement into a broader domain of consciousness which can make us aware of what we really are beneath the image of the ego ( Gunaratana and Gunaratana, 2011 ). This detached awareness reduces an individual’s clinging to the contents of their mind that are associated with the person as themselves. Such a shift in perspective is called “re-perceiving” by Shapiro et al. (2006) , who found that this is predominantly how mindfulness works in therapy. Ultimately, the mindfulness of both Buddhism and psychology is viewed as an important way to understand the nature of the self, and to obtain spiritual well-being.
Mindfulness and the Self
In modern Western society, mindfulness is practiced, cultivated, and applied in far more diverse contexts than in the East, involving self-exploration, self-experience, and self-transformation ( Schmidt, 2011 ). Correspondingly, there are large numbers of studies concerning mindfulness and the self, linking it to self-compassion ( Neff K.D., 2003 ), self-acceptance ( Carson and Langer, 2006 ; Dryden and Still, 2006 ), self-perspective change ( Hölzel et al., 2011 ), self-consciousness ( Evans et al., 2009 ; Ghorbani et al., 2010 ), self-concept ( Crescentini and Capurso, 2015 ), self-deconstruction and reconstruction ( Dahl et al., 2015 ), self-referential processing ( Farb et al., 2007 ; Tang et al., 2015 ; Hadash et al., 2016 ), and so on. Growing numbers of studies and reports of clinical practice have suggested that mindfulness meditation practices bring about positive significant effects in reducing physical and psychological symptoms, and in improving active growth and well-being, as well as changing self-knowledge and the mode of self-referential processing. In this paper, we argue that the practices of mindfulness meditation lead to positive changes in the social-psychological functioning of the self at both a quantitative and a qualitative level, and that these quantitative and qualitative changes interact.
On the one hand, it has been suggested that engaging in mindfulness meditation practices or interventions (especially over long periods of time) is closely associated with increases in positive self-attitudes, such as non-attachment (or acceptance) ( Monteromarin et al., 2016 ), self-compassion (i.e., self-kindness, not self-criticism) ( Hollis-Walker and Colosimo, 2011 ), equanimity (not indifference) ( Desbordes et al., 2015 ), and with becoming more compassionate to the self and equally so to others. In a certain sense, some of the above positive changes in self-attitude can also be observed or described at a qualitative level. For example, it has been suggested that compassion-focused meditation can facilitate an individual’s self-kindness or sense of warmth for those people with high levels of shame and self-criticism ( Hofmann et al., 2011 ; Gilbert, 2014 ), making more shamed or self-critical people become more self-kind.
Moreover, it has been suggested that mindfulness is associated with decreasing self-identification with self-images ( Graham et al., 2009 ; Edwards, 2013 ), moderating the defensive tendencies associated with lower ego-involvement (e.g., Kernis and Goldman, 2006 ; Weinstein et al., 2009 ). Consequently, it promotes self-knowledge; i.e., the knowledge of the nature of the self and the relation between the self and the content of experience ( Jankowski and Holas, 2014 ). Further, it increases one’s ability to start experiencing a sense of the self as a transitory, interdependent, dynamic change process, rather than as a constant and unchanging entity. That is to say, it gradually changes implicit self-concepts and perspectives on the self at a qualitative level ( Dambrun and Ricard, 2011 ; Hölzel et al., 2011 ), according to which self-referential processing becomes diminished, while first-person experiencing becomes enhanced ( Hölzel et al., 2011 ). Instead of identification with a static self, there emerges a tendency to identify with the phenomenon of “experiencing” the self without psychological defense mechanisms.
In addition, mindfulness can change the mode of self-focused attention ( Jain et al., 2007 ; Heeren and Philippot, 2011 ; Campbell et al., 2012 ). It has been suggested that mindfulness meditation makes one to be fully but impartially aware, and attentive to what is occurring without judgment, investment, or antipathy for what appears, which leads to clarity and accuracy in people’s perceptions and judgments ( McIntosh, 1997 ; Ryan and Rigby, 2015 ). Within this enhanced clarity, the process of a repeatedly arising sense of self becomes observable to the meditator and facilitates a detachment from identification with the static sense of self, which has been termed “decentering” or “reperceiving” ( Shapiro et al., 2006 ; Carmody et al., 2009 ). It has been postulated that paying attention and awareness to the transitory nature of this sense of self leads to the “positive deconstruction of the self” ( Epstein, 1988 ).
The shift in self-awareness is viewed as one of the major active mechanisms of the beneficial effects of mindfulness meditation ( Tang et al., 2015 ). The non-self-referential process of the present-moment experience is also seen as a unifying metacognitive process underlying a number of candidate mindfulness mechanisms characterized by dis-identification from internal experience, such as decentering, metacognitive awareness, and re-perceiving ( Bernstein et al., 2015 ; Hadash et al., 2016 ). Following up on such studies, Vago and David (2012) proposed an “S-ART” framework (self-awareness, self-regulation, and self-transcendence) for understanding mindfulness, focusing on self-processing and the underlying neural systems, and based on existing neurocognitive research and empirical studies of mindfulness and the self. The S-ART framework uses self-processing to illustrate the complexity of the mechanisms of mindfulness that function to reduce suffering and create a sustainably healthy mind. Within this framework, mindfulness is described as reducing a distorted or biased sense of self and one’s relation to others and the external world through specific forms of mindfulness practices that develop a meta-awareness of self (self-awareness), an ability to effectively manage or alter one’s responses and impulses (self-regulation), and the development of a positive relationship between the self and others that transcends self-focused needs and increases prosocial characteristics (self-transcendence). Overall, S-ART sets out to show that mindfulness meditation practice is an effective and complex process that reduces suffering and creates a sustainably healthy mind in individual subjects.
In all, these findings suggest that mindfulness practices moderate implicit self-concepts and perspectives on the self ( Levesque and Brown, 2007 ), and encourage positive functions of the self with a shift toward more healthy profiles ( Olendzki, 2006 ; Hölzel et al., 2011 ; Crescentini and Capurso, 2015 ).
The Definition and Connotations of the Mindful Self
The above studies suggest that mindfulness works beneficially on changing self-experiencing and self-understanding, softening one’s “centered” and “substantialized” self and, instead, internalizing and integrating the essence of Buddhist psychology (e.g., the non-self, and impermanence) into one’s self-system or self-concept. To describe such a changed and mindful self, which underlies mindfulness practices as well as dispositional mindfulness, we propose a new concept: the “mindful self (MS).” Further to a series of empirical and theoretical studies of mindfulness and the self, we define MS as a mindfulness-enlightened self-view that involves an embodied integration and internalization of the essence of the non-self in the process of mindfulness meditation practices or intervention. Here, being mindful means becoming aware or paying attention to everything. It means letting nothing occur without one’s conscious being aware of it ( McIntosh, 1997 ; Rosenbaum, 2009 ), while “self-view” refers to self-understanding and self-attitude.
From the perspective of self-development, the connotations of the MS concept share some associations with terms such as “self-actualization” ( Roger, 1951 ; Maslow, 1970 ) and “ego development” ( Loevinger, 1977 ). It also shares some meanings with the higher level identified in Dabrowski’s (1964) theory of positive disintegration. The main connotations of self-actualization, ego-development, positive disintegration theory, and the mindful self (positive effects or changes of the self that are based on mindfulness meditation), are presented in Table 1 . However, there are also substantial differences between the MS and self-actualization, ego-development, the theory of positive disintegration, as well as with dispositional mindfulness and “the quiet ego” ( Bauer and Wayment, 2008 ), as discussed in the following sections.
The main connotations of MS, self-actualization, ego development, and the positive disintegration theory.
The Mindful Self and Self-actualization: The Authentic or True Self
The MS and self-actualization share some concepts, both emphasizing the importance of openness to experience, and incorporating ideas about the “here and now” and awareness. Beyond that, though, some constituents of mindfulness or Buddhist psychology are integrated into the MS, such as non-judgment, focusing on the present, non-attachment, and equanimity. An additional difference between the MS and self-actualization is in their respective underlying modes of the process of self-reference: the MS emphasizes a selfless reference process, whereas self-actualization prioritizes the self-reference process. In the Buddhist tradition, experiential self-reference is viewed as a cause of suffering, and the selfless process is seen as a key mechanism, achieved through mindfulness, with which to alleviate suffering ( Olendzki, 2006 ). The purpose of mindfulness is essentially to help people become less self-centered ( Rosenbaum, 2009 ) and to assist them in achieving cognitive transformations and obtain wisdom ( Purser and Milillo, 2014 ), ultimately culminating in an undistorted vision of the self. Thus the MS weakens the self-reference process and the position of self-identification by underlining the importance of self-flexibility, decentering, non-attachment, and equanimity; in contrast, self-actualization strengthens the value of self-identification and positive self-esteem, which can be seen from the connotation description in Table 1 . Prior studies have found evidence of some negative effects of pursuing high self-esteem and overly high self-identification. For instance, research has suggested that those with high self-esteem can be angry and aggressive toward others ( Baumeister et al., 1996 ) and become more vulnerable to depression and reduced self-conceptual clarity ( Kernis, 2005 ). High self-esteem has also been associated with self-enhancement bias ( Sedikides and Gregg, 2008 ) and a high level of narcissism ( Twenge and Campbell, 2009 ). On the other hand, evidence of the more positive effects of some Buddhist concepts is increasingly available. For example, it has been suggested that both self-compassion and mindfulness are more effective ways of helping individuals to develop a state of well-being than high self-esteem, with less ego-defensiveness and self-enhancement ( Neff, 2011 ; Ostafin et al., 2015 ).
In addition, mindfulness is closely related to authenticity ( Heppner and Kernis, 2007 ), which is also emphasized by self-actualization. It has been suggested that mindfulness enables an increase in “authentic functioning”— i.e., being aware of and regulating oneself ( Avolio and Gardner, 2005 )— and can help individuals to become more aware of one’s “true self” ( Brown and Ryan, 2003 ; Leroy et al., 2013 ). However, there are some essential differences between the mindful self and the true self, though they share some common features such as emphasizing the importance of awareness, unbiased or non-judgmental processing, and authentic behavior ( Kernis and Goldman, 2006 ). Researchers interested in the true self focus on the “psychological reality” of the true self and the consequences of the “true self” concept in everyday life ( Schlegel and Hicks, 2011 ), in which the true self is considered as a state or trait. That is to say, the true self is an entity-oriented construct. As a matter of fact, people tend to believe that the true self is discovered “within” and tend to agree with statements that the true self is “something very basic about them” and that “it can’t really be changed,” even after writing about a significant change they have observed in either themselves or a close friend ( Schlegel and Hicks, 2011 ). Correspondingly, the mindful self is a new construct based on the internalization and integration of the doctrine of “no-self,” taking the self “as a process,” which can be seen as a process of “de-entity” of the self; i.e., a process of attenuating self-entity.
The Mindful Self, Ego Development, and the Positive Disintegration Theory
The MS is also different from ego development and the positive disintegration theory. “Ego development” is conceptualized as a mature trait characterized by five implicit features: individuality, self-awareness, complexity, wholeness, and autonomy. Ego development attempts to describe the developmental stages in the ways in which individuals make meaning of their personal life experiences and the world at large ( Bailey, 2011 ). However, it lacks a clear distinction between content and form as well as any logical nature to the sequence of levels ( Broughton and Zahaykevich, 1988 ). The “theory of positive disintegration” describes an important underlying mechanism concerning mental development by highlighting the process of a positive disintegration of tension, inner conflict, and anxiety from lower to higher levels of mental life, thereby emphasizing the importance of emotion in adult self-development. Through the process of positive disintegration, adolescents gain the capacity to differentiate and then to integrate their own distinct inner experiences ( Laycraft, 2011 ). As Table 1 shows, the MS is associated with the higher levels of both ego development and the positive disintegration theory. All three concepts are closely related to self-development but from different perspectives, and the MS may represent a particular self-view underlying the higher levels of ego development and the positive disintegration theory, especially for those who grow up in a Buddhist culture and those who practice mindfulness or Chan meditation over a long period.
The Mindful Self and the Quiet Ego
The Mindful Self and Dispositional Mindfulness
“Dispositional mindfulness” refers to an individual’s capacity and tendency to abide in mindful states over time ( Brown et al., 2007 ), comprising continued well-developed attention and inhibitory control ( Stillman et al., 2014 ). It is conceptualized as a trait ( Goodall et al., 2012 ) or as a mindful personality ( Hanley, 2016 ). Operationally, the factors in Baer et al.’s (2006) Five Facet Mindfulness Questionnaire—observing, describing, acting with awareness, non-reaction to inner experience, and non-judgment of inner experience—are commonly taken to measure an individual’s dispositional mindfulness ( Baer et al., 2006 ). Many studies suggest that a higher dispositional mindfulness benefits a wide range of psychological and social outcomes, including an increase in life satisfaction, more positive affects, less negative affects ( Brown and Ryan, 2003 ), and an increase in self-esteem ( Pepping et al., 2013 ). It has also been found that dispositional mindfulness is significantly correlated with each factor in the Five Factor Model of personality ( Hanley, 2016 ).
Clearly, the MS and dispositional mindfulness are two interrelated but different concepts. As summarized above (see also Table 1 ), mindfulness practices can bring about three aspects of positive change: cognitive; behavioral (both of which are principally associated with dispositional mindfulness); and self-view and attitude (which are principally associated with the MS). Although the Five Facet Mindfulness Questionnaire includes attitudes such as acceptance and openness, it does not capture the mindful attitude directly. Rather, the MS can be seen as a “result” of mindfulness practice or as the attitudinal aspects of those who have a high trait of dispositional mindfulness. A number of studies have suggested that a positive change of attitude toward the self and others plays an important role in the psychological effects of mindfulness ( Adair, 2013 ; Xu et al., 2016 ; Yang and Mak, 2016 ). If the process of therapies based on mindfulness does not foster positive attitudes such as acceptance and equanimity, awareness itself may not contribute too much on psychological well-being ( Cardaciotto et al., 2008 ). In addition, heightened awareness can even have adverse effects on patients with panic disorder and can even have a chronic negative affect on patients with panic disorder ( Mor and Winquist, 2002 ). Therefore, it is necessary to distinguish the two aspects—behavioral tendency and attitude—in connection with mindfulness. Such separation is not only favorable with respect to studying the underlying mechanism or the relationship between mindfulness and psychological health; it is also conducive to psychological intervention and education. Studying the underlying change of attitudes behind mindfulness is of obvious value here, and the MS is a meaningful step in this undertaking.
Given the considerable differences between the MS and related concepts, we argue that it is necessary, theoretically, to propose a new concept with which to describe the positive changes to the self that are associated with mindfulness meditation practices or interventions. As a definition, the MS is conceptualized as a mindfulness-enlightened self-view and attitude attained via a process of internalizing and integrating some thoughts from Buddhist psychology into one’s self-system, summarized as follows. First, the MS acknowledges that human beings have many basic desires and needs, materially and spiritually, because nobody can be without needs, desires, or discrimination in their worldly life. But, secondly, the MS emphasizes that we should not over-identify or become overly attached to one’s various desires and needs, no matter how positive or negative they are. Thirdly, the MS lays weight on understanding the dependent, impermanent essence of the self, viewing it as a flow process, or simply as a mental phenomenon rather than as an entity, which seems to be some of the important elements involved in becoming a person ( Rogers, 1961 ). That is, a mindful person no longer treats the content of experience as objective facts and as a direct read-out of reality ( Jankowski and Holas, 2014 ). Fourthly, the MS emphasizes the significance of elaborated self-awareness and self-flexibility, and the attitude of an “ordinary mind” in promoting the positive function of the self and maintaining mental health. Thus, fifthly, the MS encourages people to change their perspective on the self, viewing the self as a process instead of an “entity” or product of reification, in which mindfulness constitutes a facilitator for “I-self” over “me-self” experience as people grapple with their relative realities; it is a resource for organizing behavior by supporting the synthetic tendencies of self-as-process ( Ryan and Rigby, 2015 ).
As far as the secular individual is concerned, we can not live in the absolute level of reality that has the characteristic or the true nature of the “empty self” or “no-self.” In our worldly lives, we can not live in the absolute level of non-dualism and indiscrimination. The aim of mindfulness practice for secular people is not to transcend the cycle of life and death that is proclaimed by Buddhism as a religion. Instead, the significance of internalizing and integrating the essence of Buddhist psychology organically into one’s self-system lies in enlightening the mind to wisdom such as non-attachment, let-going to alleviate our suffering, and coping with the uncertain challenges of life. We can be mindfully aware of our selves and experiences at the relative level, while simultaneously recognizing the absolute reality of phenomena ( Gyatso, 2002 ). Presumably, in fact, mindfulness fully practiced will lead one along the “middle way” ( Hanh, 1999 )—i.e., seeking a path between the self and no-self. We conceptualize the aim here as the mindful self, which takes the self as a process with awareness. The more self-as-process is active, the more the person experiences his or her behaviors as volitional and autonomous, and the more his or her actions are experienced as wholehearted and authentic ( Ryan and Rigby, 2015 ).
The Ms and its Psychological Functioning
Based on the above analysis, we posit that the MS, as a mindfulness-edified self-view, is the primary cause or mechanism behind the stable positive changes attained through mindfulness meditation practices or interventions. There are several reasons to believe that the MS is a robust indicator in determining the significant positive effects and their relationships with mental health problems. On the one hand, the main aim of mindfulness is to cultivate a meditative attitude in order to gain a peace of mind based on the embodied insight of impermanence ( anicca ) or not-self ( anatta ) and suffering or pervasive “unsatisfactoriness” ( dukkha ) ( Khong, 2009 ). As Khong (2009 , p. 14) elucidates:
“This brings us to one of the most important teachings of the Buddha, that gaining insight into the ontological nature of reality can bring about a change of attitude at the individual level. The transformation of perspective involves adopting a meditative attitude of non-attachment, acceptance and letting be, and letting go. Without this change in attitude, understanding the dukkha [suffering] could become merely an intellectual exercise.”
On the other hand, according to the teachings of the Chinese Chan (Zen) school, the foremost means of liberating the mind is to treat “the lost/deluded self” directly. Chan Buddhism suggests that, provided the nature of the self has changed harmoniously and is fully enlightened; the psychological symptoms of mental problems will disappear or diminish as a matter of course. As the originator of the Chan school of Buddhism expounded after attaining enlightenment:
“The mind has the capacity for great things, and is not meant for practicing petty ways. Do not talk about emptiness with your mouth all day and in your mind fail to cultivate the conduct that you talk of …When you become enlightened in a sudden insight, you do not grasp onto the cultivation of external things. When your own mind constantly gives rise to right views, afflictions and defilement can never stain you. That is what is meant by seeing your own nature” ( Hui-Neng, 2005 ).
Thus, traditional mindfulness meditation emphasizes the significance of changing attitudes and the most fundamental knowledge of oneself in the practice or intervention of mindfulness meditation. Correspondingly, attitudes such as non-attachment, equanimity, “not doing,” and self-compassion are the most important components of the MS. Several studies have found that these attitudes play an important role in modulating the effects of mindfulness and psychological health. For example, it has been shown that non-attachment substantially mediated the links between facets of mindfulness and the outcome variables of satisfaction with life and life effectiveness ( Sahdra et al., 2015 ). Similarly, other studies have found that self-compassion moderated the relationship between self-stigma content and life satisfaction among people living with HIV ( Yang and Mak, 2016 ). Moreover, a number of studies have suggested that expressing compassion, kindness, or love to oneself helps to reduce the tendency of hostility or anger to others ( Analayo, 2004 ), increases positive affects and decreases negative affects ( Hofmann et al., 2011 ), and decreases shame and self-criticism ( Gilbert, 2009 ). Furthermore, some studies have discovered that self-compassion is a stronger predictor of well-being than mindfulness ( Van Dam et al., 2011 ; Woodruff et al., 2014 ). In addition, equanimity, or an equal and receptive attitude toward all beings, is also an important concept that captures, potentially, a significant psychological element in the improvement of well-being ( Desbordes et al., 2015 ). Therefore, we infer that the MS is an important intermediary between mindfulness intervention and mental health problems, and in promoting well-being.
In addition, and more generally, it would be of benefit to consider the MS as a particular standard of psychological maturity in the context of self-development. Psychological standards of maturity involve the development of favorable attitudes toward the self, others, and work-related motives, and of a behavior-guiding system of values ( Greenberger and Sørensen, 1974 ). The positive changes based on mindfulness that are able to meet the criteria of psychological maturity, as summarized by Golovey et al. (2015) , include qualities or traits of responsibility, reflexiveness, awareness, self-acceptance and self-respect, integrity and congruence, and so on. A number of studies have suggested that mindfulness meditation makes one more mature and leads to more autonomous behavior ( Levesque and Brown, 2007 ; Ireland, 2013 ). It is certainly clear that mindfulness practice is associated with awareness and self-acceptance, but it has also been found that a higher level of mindfulness is connected to more self-congruence, reflected in a higher concordance between implicit (non-conscious) and explicit (conscious) assessments of self-related attributes ( Thrash and Elliot, 2002 ; Brown and Ryan, 2003 ). Accordingly, and further to the comparison of the MS and self-actualization above, we submit the MS as a valid, useable concept in this context and a more appropriate indicator than self-actualization to describe and predict the higher level of self-development of those who grow up in the culture of Buddhism and those who engage in meditation in the long term.
Extensive evidence exists to suggest that cultivating a mindful or meditative attitude toward oneself and others, which we have conceptualized as the MS, is of great benefit to one’s health and well-being. As a theoretical prediction based on a review of empirical research, we posit that the MS can also be an important intermediary between mindfulness intervention and mental health problems, and in promoting well-being. More generally, we propose that the MS is an applicable concept with which to describe and predict the higher level of self-development of those who grow up in a Buddhist culture and those who engage in a long-term practice of mindfulness meditation. However, further empirical study is required. In particular, the basic components of the MS, as well as its incremental and predictive validity, need to be constructed and examined by investigating the self-views and attitudes of those people who are deemed to possess a high level of mindfulness.
Author Contributions
The design and writing of this paper was completed by QX. WH and CY took part in a discussion. J-yY was mainly engaged in the process of design, revision, and discussion.
Conflict of Interest Statement
The authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
Funding. This research was supported by Chinese ministry of education humanities and social science research project (17XJC190006) and Chongqing University of Arts and Sciences (Z2016JY19).
- Adair K. C. (2013). Is Mindfulness A Non-Judgmental Stance? Master thesis, University of North Carolina at Chapel Hil; Chapel Hill, NC. [ Google Scholar ]
- Analayo B. (2004). Satipatthana: The Direct Path to Realization. Cambridge: Windhorse Publications. [ Google Scholar ]
- Atkins P. W. B., Styles R., Atkins P. W. B., Styles R. (2015). Mindfulness, Identity and Work: Mindfulness Training Creates A More Flexible Sense of Self. Mindfulness in Organizations: Foundations, Research, and Applications. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [ Google Scholar ]
- Avolio B. J., Gardner W. L. (2005). Authentic leadership development: getting to the root of positive forms of leadership. Leadersh. Q. 16 315–338. 10.1016/j.leaqua.2005.03.001 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Baer R. A., Smith G. T., Hopkins J., Krietemeyer J., Toney L. (2006). Using self-report assessment methods to explore facets of mindfulness. Assessment 13 27–45. 10.1177/1073191105283504 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Bailey C. L. (2011). An examination of the relationships between ego development, dabrowski’s theory of positive disintegration, and the behavioral characteristics of gifted adolescents. Gift. Child Q. 55 208–222. 10.1177/0016986211412180 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Bauer J. J., Wayment H. A. (eds) (2008). “The psychology of the quiet ego,” in Transcending Self-Interest: Psychological Explorations of the Quiet Ego (Washington, DC: American Psychological Association; ) 7–19. 10.1037/11771-001 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Baumeister R. F., Smart L., Boden J. M. (1996). Relation of threatened egotism to violence and aggression: the dark side of high self-esteem. Psychol. Rev. 103 5–33. 10.1037/0033-295X.103.1.5 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Berkson M. A. (2005). Conceptions of self/no-self and modes of connection comparative soteriological structures in classical Chinese thought. J. Relig. Ethics 33 293–331. 10.1111/j.1467-9795.2005.00190.x [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Bernstein A., Hadash Y., Lichtash Y., Tanay G., Shepherd K., Fresco D. M. (2015). Decentering and Related Constructs: A Critical Review and Metacognitive Processes Model. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 10 599–617. 10.1177/1745691615594577 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Bishop S. R., Lau M., Shapiro S., Carlson L., Anderson N. D., Carmody J., et al. (2004). Mindfulness: a proposed operational definition. Clin. Psychol. Sci. Pract. 11 230–241. 10.1093/clipsy.bph077 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Broughton J. M., Zahaykevich M. K. (1988). Ego and Ideology: A Critical Review of Loevinger’s Theory. New York, NY: Springer. [ Google Scholar ]
- Brown K. W., Ryan R. M. (2003). The benefits of being present: mindfulness and its role in psychological well-being. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 84 822–848. 10.1037/0022-3514.84.4.822 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Brown K. W., Ryan R. M., Creswell J. D. (2007). Mindfulness: theoretical foundations and evidence for its salutary effects. Psychol. Inq. 18 211–237. 10.1080/10478400701598298 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Campbell T. S., Labelle L. E., Bacon S. L., Faris P., Carlson L. E. (2012). Impact of Mindfulness-Based Stress Reduction (MBSR) on attention, rumination and resting blood pressure in women with cancer: a waitlist-controlled study. J. Behav. Med. 35 262–271. 10.1007/s10865-011-9357-1 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Cardaciotto L. A., Herbert J. D., Forman E. M., Moitra E., Farrow V. (2008). The assessment of present-moment awareness and acceptance: the Philadelphia Mindfulness Scale. Assessment 15 204–223. 10.1177/1073191107311467 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Carmody J., Baer R. A., Lb Lykins E., Olendzki N. (2009). An empirical study of the mechanisms of mindfulness in a mindfulness-based stress reduction program. J. Clin. Psychol. 65 613–626. 10.1002/jclp.20579 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Carson S. H., Langer E. J. (2006). Mindfulness and self-acceptance. J. Ration. Emot. Cogn. Behav. Ther. 24 29–43. 10.1007/s10942-006-0022-5 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Chan W. (2008). Psychological attachment, no-self and Chan Buddhist mind therapy. Contemp. Buddh. 9 253–264. 10.1080/14639940802556586 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Crescentini C., Capurso V. (2015). Mindfulness meditation and explicit and implicit indicators of personality and self-concept changes. Front. Psychol. 6:44. 10.3389/fpsyg.2015.00044 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Dabrowski K. (1964). Positive disintegration. J. Am. Med. Assoc. 190 1081 10.1001/jama.1964.03070250063033 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Dahl C. J., Lutz A., Davidson R. J. (2015). Reconstructing and deconstructing the self: cognitive mechanisms in meditation practice. Trends Cogn. Sci. 19 515–523. 10.1016/j.tics.2015.07.001 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Dambrun M., Ricard M. (2011). Self-centeredness and selflessness: a theory of self-based psychological functioning and its consequences for happiness. Rev. Gen. Psychol. 15 138–157. 10.1037/a0023059 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Desbordes G., Gard T., Hoge E. A., Hölzel B. K., Kerr C., Lazar S. W., et al. (2015). Moving beyond mindfulness: defining equanimity as an outcome measure in meditation and contemplative research. Mindfulness 6 356–372. 10.1007/s12671-013-0269-8 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Donner S. E. (2010). Self or no self: views from self psychology and Buddhism in a postmodern context. Smith Coll. Stud. Soc. Work 80 215–227. 10.1080/00377317.2010.486361 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Dryden W., Still A. (2006). Historical aspects of mindfulness and self-acceptance in psychotherapy. J. Ration. Emot. Cogn. Behav. Ther. 24 3–28. 10.1007/s10942-006-0026-1 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Edge H. L. (2014). “Does meditation give us unique insight into ultimate reality? the ethical aim of Buddhism,” in Meditation–Neuroscientific Approaches and Philosophical Implications eds Schmidt S., Walach H. (Berlin: Springer; ) 271–295. [ Google Scholar ]
- Edwards S. D. (2013). Influence of a self-identification meditation intervention on psychological and neurophysiologic variables. J. Psychol. Afr. 23 69–76. [ Google Scholar ]
- Engler J. (1984). Therapeutic aims in psychotherapy and meditation: developmental stages in the representation of self. J. Transpers. Psychol. 16 25–62. [ Google Scholar ]
- Epstein M. (1988). The deconstruction of the self: ego and “egolessness” in Buddhist insight meditation. J. Transpers. Psychol. 20 61–69. [ Google Scholar ]
- Evans D. R., Baer R. A., Segerstrom S. C. (2009). The effects of mindfulness and self-consciousness on persistence. Pers. Individ. Diff. 47 379–382. 10.1016/j.paid.2009.03.026 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Falkenström F. (2003). A Buddhist contribution to the psychoanalytic psychology of self. Int. J. Psychoanal. 84(Pt 6) 1551–1568. 10.1516/XH6D-2YLY-P2JV-9VRC [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Farb N. A., Segal Z. V., Mayberg H., Bean J., McKeon D., Fatima Z., et al. (2007). Attending to the present: mindfulness meditation reveals distinct neural modes of self-reference. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 2 313–322. 10.1093/scan/nsm030 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Gallagher S., Shear J. E. (1999). Models of the Self. Exeter: Imprint Academic. [ Google Scholar ]
- Germer C. K., Siegel R. D. (2012). Wisdom and Compassion in Psychotherapy: Deepening Mindfulness in Clinical Practice. New York City, NY: Guilford Publications. [ Google Scholar ]
- Gethin R. (2011). On some definitions of mindfulness. Contemp. Buddh. 12 263–279. 10.1080/14639947.2011.564843 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Ghorbani N., Cunningham C. J., Watson P. (2010). Comparative analysis of integrative self-knowledge, mindfulness, and private self-consciousness in predicting responses to stress in Iran. Int. J. Psychol. 45 147–154. 10.1080/00207590903473768 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Gilbert P. (2009). Introducing compassion-focused therapy. Adv. Psychiatr. Treat. 15 199–208. 10.1192/apt.bp.107.005264 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Gilbert P. (2014). The origins and nature of compassion focused therapy. Br. J. Clin. Psychol. 53 6–41. 10.1111/bjc.12043 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Goldstein J. (2002). One Dharma: The Emerging Western Buddhism. San Franciso, CA: Harper. [ Google Scholar ]
- Golovey L. A., Manukyan V. R., Strizhitskaya O. Y. (2015). Formation of personality psychological maturity and adulthood crises. Psychol. Russ. State Art 8 99–112. 10.11621/pir.2015.0209 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Goodall K., Trejnowska A., Darling S. (2012). The relationship between dispositional mindfulness, attachment security and emotion regulation. Pers. Individ. Diff. 52 622–626. 10.1016/j.paid.2011.12.008 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Graham J. R., Hayes S. A., Erisman S. M., Roemer L. (2009). “The relationship between mindfulness and anxiety in black self-identified individuals,” in Poster Presented at the 43rd Annual Meeting of the Association for Behavioral and Cognitive Therapies New York, NY. [ Google Scholar ]
- Greenberger E., Sørensen A. B. (1974). Toward a concept of psychosocial maturity. J. Youth Adolesc. 3 329–358. 10.1007/BF02214746 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Gunaratana B., Gunaratana H. (2011). Mindfulness in Plain English. New York City, NY: Simon and Schuster. [ Google Scholar ]
- Gyatso T. (2002). Dzogchen: Heart Essence of the Great Perfection. Trans eds Gaffney P., Jinpa T., Barron R. (Ithaca, NY: Snow Lion Publications; ). [ Google Scholar ]
- Hadash Y., Plonsker R., Vago D. R., Bernstein A. (2016). Experiential self-referential and selfless processing in mindfulness and mental health: conceptual model and implicit measurement methodology. Psychol. Assess. 28 856–869. 10.1037/pas0000300 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Han S., Gu X., Mao L., Ge J., Wang G., Ma Y. (2010). Neural substrates of self-referential processing in Chinese Buddhists. Soc. Cogn. Affect. Neurosci. 5 332–339. 10.1093/scan/nsp027 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hanh T. N. (1999). The Heart of the Buddha’s Teaching: Transforming Suffering Into Peace, Joy & Liberation: The Four Noble Truths, the Noble Eightfold Path, and Other Basic Buddhist Teachings. Portland, OR: Broadway Books. [ Google Scholar ]
- Hanley A. W. (2016). The mindful personality: associations between dispositional mindfulness and the five factor model of personality. Pers. Individ. Diff. 91 154–158. 10.1016/j.paid.2015.11.054 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Harrington N., Pickles C. (2009). Mindfulness and cognitive behavioral therapy: a rebuttal. J. Cogn. Psychother. 23 333–335. 10.1891/0889-8391.23.4.333 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hayes S. C., Luoma J. B., Bond F. W., Masuda A., Lillis J. (2006). Acceptance and commitment therapy: model, processes and outcomes. Behav. Res. Ther. 44 1–25. 10.1016/j.brat.2005.06.006 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hayes S. C., Wilson K. G. (2003). Mindfulness: method and process. Clin. Psychol. Sci. Pract. 10 161–165. 10.1093/clipsy.bpg018 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Heeren A., Philippot P. (2011). Changes in ruminative thinking mediate the clinical benefits of mindfulness: preliminary findings. Mindfulness 2 8–13. 10.1007/s12671-010-0037-y [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Heppner W. L., Kernis M. H. (2007). “Quiet Ego” functioning: the complementary roles of mindfulness, authenticity, and secure high self-esteem. Psychol. Inq. 18 248–251. 10.1080/10478400701598330 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hofmann S. G., Grossman P., Hinton D. E. (2011). Loving-kindness and compassion meditation: potential for psychological interventions. Clin. Psychol. Rev. 31 1126–1132. 10.1016/j.cpr.2011.07.003 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hollis-Walker L., Colosimo K. (2011). Mindfulness, self-compassion, and happiness in non-meditators: a theoretical and empirical examination. Pers. Individ. Diff. 50 222–227. 10.1016/j.paid.2010.09.033 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hölzel B. K., Lazar S. W., Gard T., Schuman-Olivier Z., Vago D. R., Ott U. (2011). How does mindfulness meditation work? Proposing mechanisms of action from a conceptual and neural perspective. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 6 537–559. 10.1177/1745691611419671 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Hosking P. (2007). “Compassion: what is in a word,” in The Power of Compassion: An Exploration of the Psychology of Compassion in the 21st Century ed. Kostanski M. (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing; ) 2–13. [ Google Scholar ]
- Hui-Neng (2005). The Platform Sutra. Shenyang: Liaoning education press. [ Google Scholar ]
- Ie A., Haller C. S., Langer E. J., Courvoisier D. S. (2013). Mindful multitasking: the relationship between mindful flexibility and media multitasking. Comput. Hum. Behav. 28 1526–1532. 10.1016/j.chb.2012.03.022 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Ireland M. J. (2013). Meditation and psychological health: modeling theoretically derived predictors, processes, and outcomes. Mindfulness 4 362–374. 10.1007/s12671-012-0136-z [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Jain S., Shapiro S. L., Swanick S., Roesch S. C., Mills P. J., Bell I., et al. (2007). A randomized controlled trial of mindfulness meditation versus relaxation training: effects on distress, positive states of mind, rumination, and distraction. Ann. Behav. Med. 33 11–21. 10.1207/s15324796abm3301_2 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Jankowski T., Holas P. (2014). Metacognitive model of mindfulness. Conscious. Cogn. 28 64–80. 10.1016/j.concog.2014.06.005 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kabat-Zinn J. (2003). Mindfulness-based interventions in context: past, present, and future. Clin. Psychol. 10 144–156. 10.1093/clipsy.bpg016 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kabat-Zinn J. (2005). Coming to Our Senses: Healing Ourselves and the World Through Mindfulness. Hachette: Piatkus. [ Google Scholar ]
- Kabat-Zinn J., Hanh T. N. (2009). Full Catastrophe Living: Using the Wisdom of Your Body and Mind to Face Stress, Pain, and Illness. New York, NY: Random House. [ Google Scholar ]
- Kernis M. H. (2005). Measuring self-esteem in context: the importance of stability of self-esteem in psychological functioning. J. Pers. 73 1569–1605. 10.1111/j.1467-6494.2005.00359.x [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kernis M. H., Goldman B. M. (2006). A multicomponent conceptualization of authenticity: theory and research. Adv. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 38 283–357. 10.1016/S0065-2601(06)38006-9 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Khong B. S. L. (2009). Expanding the understanding of mindfulness: seeing the tree and the forest. Humanist. Psychol. 37 117–136. 10.1080/08873260902892006 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Kudesia R. S., Nyima V. T. (2014). Mindfulness contextualized: an integration of buddhist and neuropsychological approaches to cognition. Mindfulness 6 1–16. [ Google Scholar ]
- Laycraft K. (2011). Theory of positive disintegration as a model of adolescent development. Nonlinear Dyn. Psychol. Life Sci. 15 29–52. [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Leclerc G., Lefrançois R., Dubé M., Hébert R., Gaulin P. (1998). The self-actualization concept: a content validation. J. Soc. Behav. Pers. 13 69–84. [ Google Scholar ]
- Leroy H., Anseel F., Dimitrova N. G., Sels L. (2013). Mindfulness, authentic functioning, and work engagement: a growth modeling approach. J. Vocat. Behav. 82 238–247. 10.1016/j.jvb.2013.01.012 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Levesque C., Brown K. W. (2007). Mindfulness as a moderator of the effect of implicit motivational self-concept on day-to-day behavioral motivation. Motiv. Emot. 31 284–299. 10.1007/s11031-007-9075-8 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Loevinger J. (1977). Ego Development: Conceptions and Theories. Candor, NY: Telos Press. [ Google Scholar ]
- Lomas T., Edginton T., Cartwright T., Ridge D. (2015). Cultivating equanimity through mindfulness meditation: a mixed methods enquiry into the development of decentring capabilities in men. Int. J. Wellbeing 5 88–106. 10.5502/ijw.v5i3.7 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Martin J. R. (1997). Mindfulness: a proposed common factor. J. Psychother. Integration 7 291–312. 10.1080/00223891.2015.1095761 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Maslow A. H. (1970). Maslow Motivation and Personality. New York, NY: Harper & Row. [ Google Scholar ]
- McIntosh W. D. (1997). East meets west: parallels between zen Buddhism and social psychology. Int. J. Psychol. Relig. 7 37–52. 10.1207/s15327582ijpr0701_5 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Mikulas W. L. (2011). Mindfulness: significant common confusions. Mindfulness 2 1–7. 10.1007/s12671-010-0036-z [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Monteromarin J., Pueblaguedea M., Herreramercadal P., Cebolla A., Soler J., Demarzo M., et al. (2016). Psychological effects of a 1-month meditation retreat on experienced meditators: the role of non-attachment. Front. Psychol. 7:1935. 10.3389/fpsyg.2016.01935 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Mor N., Winquist J. (2002). Self-focused attention and negative affect: a meta-analysis. Psychol. Bull. 128 638–662. 10.1037/0033-2909.128.4.638 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Neff K. (2003). Self-compassion: an alternative conceptualization of a healthy attitude toward oneself. Self Identity 2 85–101. 10.1080/15298860309032 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Neff K. D. (2003). The development and validation of a scale to measure self-compassion. Self Identity 2 223–250. 10.1080/15298860309027 26979311 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Neff K. D. (2011). Self-compassion, self-esteem, and well-being. Soc. Pers. Psychol. Compass 5 1–12. 10.1111/j.1751-9004.2010.00330.x [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Olendzki A. (2006). “The transformative impact of non-self,” in Buddhist Thought and Applied Psychological Research: Transcending the Boundaries eds Nauriyal D. K., Drummond M. S., Lal Y. B. (New York, NY: Routledge; ) 250–261. [ Google Scholar ]
- Olendzki A. (2010). Unlimiting Mind: The Radically Experiential Psychology of Buddhism . Boston, MA: Wisdom. [ Google Scholar ]
- Ostafin B. D., Robinson M. D., Meier B. P. (2015). Handbook of Mindfulness and Self-Regulation. New York, NY: Springer. [ Google Scholar ]
- Pepping C. A., O’Donovan A., Davis P. J. (2013). The positive effects of mindfulness on self-esteem. J. Posit. Psychol. 8 376–386. 10.1080/17439760.2013.807353 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Purser R. E., Milillo J. (2014). Mindfulness revisited: a Buddhist-based conceptualization. J. Manag. Inq. 24 3–24. 10.1177/1056492614532315 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Rigby C. S., Schultz P. P., Ryan R. M. (2014). “Mindfulness, interest-taking, and self-regulation,” in The Wiley Blackwell Handbook of Mindfulness eds Ie A., Ngnoumen C. T., Langer E. J. (Malden, MA: Wiley Blackwell; ) 216–235. [ Google Scholar ]
- Roger C. R. (1951). Client-Centered Therapy: Its Current Practice, Implications and Theory. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt. [ Google Scholar ]
- Rogers R. C. (1961). On Becoming a Person: A Therapist’s View of Psychotherapy. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin Company. [ Google Scholar ]
- Rosenbaum R. (2009). Empty mindfulness in humanistic psychotherapy. Humanist. Psychol. 37 207–221. 10.1080/08873260902892196 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Rubin J. B. (1996). “Psychoanalysis and Buddhism,” in Psychotherapy and Buddhism ed. Safran J. (Berlin: Springer; ) 155–188. 10.1007/978-1-4899-7280-4_10 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Rubin J. B. (2013). Psychotherapy and Buddhism: Toward an Integration. Berlin: Springer Science & Business Media. [ Google Scholar ]
- Ryan R. M., Rigby C. S. (2015). Did the Buddha Have a self? Handbook of Mindfulness: Theory, Research, and Practice. New York, NY: Guilford Press; 245. [ Google Scholar ]
- Sahdra B., Ciarrochi J., Parker P. (2015). Nonattachment and mindfulness: related but distinct constructs. Psychol. Assess. 28 819–829. 10.1037/pas0000264 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Sahdra B. K., Shaver P. R., Brown K. W. (2010). A scale to measure nonattachment: a Buddhist complement to Western research on attachment and adaptive functioning. J. Pers. Assess. 92 116–127. 10.1080/00223890903425960 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Schlegel R. J., Hicks J. A. (2011). The true self and psychological health: emerging evidence and future directions. Soc. Pers. Psychol. Compass 5 989–1003. 10.1111/j.1751-9004.2011.00401.x [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Schmidt S. (2011). “Mindfulness in east and west–is it the same?,” in Neuroscience, Consciousness and Spirituality eds Walach H., Schmidt S., Jonas W. (Dordrecht: Springer; ) 23–38. 10.1007/978-94-007-2079-4_2 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Sedikides C., Gregg A. P. (2008). Self-enhancement: food for thought. Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 3 102–116. 10.1111/j.1745-6916.2008.00068.x [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Sedikides C., Spencer S. J. (2007). The Self. Hove: Psychology Press. [ Google Scholar ]
- Shapiro S. L., Carlson L. E., Astin J. A., Freedman B. (2006). Mechanisms of mindfulness. J. Clin. Psychol. 62 373–386. 10.1002/jclp.20237 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Stillman C. M., Feldman H., Wambach C. G., Howard J. H., Jr., Howard D. V. (2014). Dispositional mindfulness is associated with reduced implicit learning. Conscious. Cogn. 28 141–150. 10.1016/j.concog.2014.07.002 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Tang Y. Y., Holzel B. K., Posner M. I. (2015). The neuroscience of mindfulness meditation. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 16 213–225. 10.1038/nrn3916 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Thrash T. M., Elliot A. J. (2002). Implicit and self-attributed achievement motives: concordance and predictive validity. J. Pers. 70 729–756. 10.1111/1467-6494.05022 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Twenge J., Campbell K. (2009). The Narcissism Epidemic: Living in the Age of Entitlement. New York City, NY: Simon and Schuster. [ Google Scholar ]
- Vago D. R., David S. A. (2012). Self-awareness, self-regulation, and self-transcendence (S-ART): a framework for understanding the neurobiological mechanisms of mindfulness. Front. Hum. Neurosci. 6:296. 10.3389/fnhum.2012.00296 [ DOI ] [ PMC free article ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Van Dam N. T., Sheppard S. C., Forsyth J. P., Earleywine M. (2011). Self-compassion is a better predictor than mindfulness of symptom severity and quality of life in mixed anxiety and depression. J. Anxiety Disord. 25 123–130. 10.1016/j.janxdis.2010.08.011 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Weinstein N., Brown K. W., Ryan R. M. (2009). A multi-method examination of the effects of mindfulness on stress attribution, coping, and emotional well-being. J. Res. Pers. 43 374–385. 10.1016/j.jrp.2008.12.008 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Williams J. M. G., Kabat-Zinn J. (2011). Mindfulness: diverse perspectives on its meaning, origins, and multiple applications at the intersection of science and dharma. Contemp. Buddh. 12 1–18. 10.1080/14639947.2011.564811 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Woodruff S. C., Glass C. R., Arnkoff D. B., Crowley K. J., Hindman R. K., Hirschhorn E. W. (2014). Comparing self-compassion, mindfulness, and psychological inflexibility as predictors of psychological health. Mindfulness 5 410–421. 10.1007/s12671-013-0195-9 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Xu W., Oei T. P., Liu X., Wang X., Ding C. (2016). The moderating and mediating roles of self-acceptance and tolerance to others in the relationship between mindfulness and subjective well-being. J. Health Psychol. 21:1446. 10.1177/1359105314555170 [ DOI ] [ PubMed ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Xuan J. F., Krägeloh C. U., Medvedev O. N., Billington D. R., Jin Y. J., Siegert R. J. (2016). Assessing mechanisms of mindfulness: improving the precision of the nonattachment scale using a rasch model. Mindfulness 7 1082–1091. 10.1007/s12671-016-0546-4 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- Yang X., Mak W. W. S. (2016). The differential moderating roles of self-compassion and mindfulness in self-stigma and well-being among people living with mental illness or HIV. Mindfulness 8 595–602. 10.1007/s12671-016-0635-4 [ DOI ] [ Google Scholar ]
- View on publisher site
- PDF (230.0 KB)
- Collections
Similar articles
Cited by other articles, links to ncbi databases.
- Download .nbib .nbib
- Format: AMA APA MLA NLM
IMAGES
VIDEO
COMMENTS
Organizational Behavior. Developing Self-A wareness: Learning Processes for. Self- and Interpersonal Growth. Manuel London, 1Valerie I. Sessa,2. and Loren A. Shelley 2. 1 College of Business ...
Self-awareness—how we see ourselves and the effects we have on our environment—influences our behavior and the type of person we want to become. This article examines recent research and areas of practice that address the meaning of self-awareness and how it develops over time. We build on extant comprehensive reviews of the literature to define self-awareness and its accuracy, measurement ...
The literature on self-awareness is characterized by multiple definitions (Sutton, 2016; Williams, 2008), and rarely does the literature recognize the complexity of the construct (Sutton et al., 2015).Self-awareness is frequently confused with concepts such as self-consciousness and self-knowledge, both of which are regularly discussed and explored interchangeably alongside self-awareness ...
The three distinct types of self-awareness benefits identified here lend support to Brown et al.'s (2007) review of the beneficial effects of mindfulness and extend their applicability to other conceptualizations of self-awareness. For example, the acceptance scale reflects the improved social interaction quality that Brown et al identified.
This paper aims to review the concept of Emotional Intelligence systematically. In essence, Emotional Intelligence pertains to our capacity to identify, comprehend, and regulate our own emotions ...
Self-awareness represents the capacity of becoming the object of one's own attention. In this state. one actively identifies, processes, and stores information about the self. This paper ...
1.1 Research Finding (1) To compare self-awareness behaviour of students between gender and ages. Also, what is the effect of students who study with the social and emotional intelligence model and the students who study with the normal learning model? (2) What is the effect on the development of self-awareness among students at different time?
1 INTRODUCTION. Self-awareness can be defined as the ability to take oneself as the object of awareness (Morin, 2011).Although this definition may suggest the idea of a unitary self that acts as both observer and object of awareness, in reality there is a multiplicity of self-processes included in this self-model, with different features being at the focus of awareness at any given time ...
The papers in this special issue can be divided into three main groups. The first consists of four papers discussing the question whether (i) the minimal self is best understood and defined relationally, that is in terms of social interactions; or rather (ii) the minimal self is a tacit, non-socially grounded, experiential self-awareness.
This paper analyzes studies of mindfulness and the self, with the aim of deepening our understanding of the potential benefits of mindfulness and meditation for mental health and well-being. Our review of empirical research reveals that positive changes in attitudes toward the self and others as a result of mindfulness-enabled practices can ...