• Search Menu
  • Sign in through your institution
  • Advance articles
  • Analysis Author Guidelines
  • Analysis Reviews Author Guidelines
  • Submission site
  • Why Publish with Analysis?
  • About Analysis
  • About The Analysis Trust
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Journals Career Network
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Dispatch Dates
  • Terms and Conditions
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Article Contents

  • 1. Methodology
  • 2. Some experiments
  • 3. Objections
  • 4. Conclusion
  • < Previous

An Empirical Refutation of ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Paul Henne, Vladimir Chituc, Felipe De Brigard, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, An Empirical Refutation of ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’, Analysis , Volume 76, Issue 3, July 2016, Pages 283–290, https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anw041

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

Most philosophers assume that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’, and most of them hold that this principle is true not only universally but also analytically or conceptually. Some skeptics deny this principle, although they often admit some related one. In this article, we show how new empirical evidence bolsters the skeptics’ arguments. We then defend the skeptical view against some objections to the empirical evidence and to its effect on the traditional principle. In light of the new evidence, we conclude that philosophers should stop unconditionally assuming that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’.

Email alerts

Citing articles via.

  • Author Guidelines
  • Contact Analysis Trust
  • X (formerly Twitter)
  • Recommend to your Library

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1467-8284
  • Print ISSN 0003-2638
  • Copyright © 2024 The Analysis Trust
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

An Analysis of Recent Empirical Data on ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’

  • Published: 08 August 2017
  • Volume 46 , pages 57–67, ( 2018 )

Cite this article

experimental philosophy ought implies can

  • Yishai Cohen 1  

354 Accesses

7 Citations

1 Altmetric

Explore all metrics

Recent experimental studies dispute the position that commonsense morality accepts ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’ (OIC), the view that, necessarily, if an agent ought to perform some action, then she can perform that action. This paper considers and supports explanations for the results of these studies on the hypothesis that OIC is intuitive and true.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save.

  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime

Price includes VAT (Russian Federation)

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Rent this article via DeepDyve

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

“ought implies can,” framing effects, and “empirical refutations”.

experimental philosophy ought implies can

A Defense of the Objective/Subjective Moral Ought Distinction

What matters when judging intentionality—moral content or normative status testing the rational scientist model of the side-effect.

An objective obligation is one that depends upon the normatively relevant facts, regardless of whether the agent has access to those facts. For instance, suppose that, unbeknownst to Robert, pressing the elevator button will result in a deadly explosion. All other things being equal, Robert has an objective obligation to refrain from pressing the button, even if he is not aware of the consequences of pressing the button. By contrast, a subjective obligation is one that depends upon the evidence available to the agent. For instance, if Robert has a justified false belief that pressing the elevator button will result in a deadly explosion, then (all other things being equal) Robert has a subjective obligation to refrain from pressing the button. Since it is possible for an agent to form a justified false belief that they can ϕ , it is possible for an agent to have a subjective obligation that they cannot in fact fulfill. For this reason, OIC is formulated in terms of an objective obligation (cf. Vranas 2007 and Graham 2011 ).

Other formulations of OIC consider ‘ought’ to refer to an objective, pro tanto obligation, rather than an all-things-considered obligation (cf. Vranas 2007 ). This difference is peripheral to the discussion at hand.

A referee rightly notes that this distinction is not sufficiently fine-grained for cases in which an agent is no longer able to do something but can nevertheless regain this ability (at least under a certain conception of abilities). Since none of the vignettes considered in this paper involve an agent who can regain a lost ability, this distinction is arguably sufficiently fine-grained for the purpose of evaluating the experimental studies under consideration.

Alicke’s theory may receive support from the hypothesis that affect contributes to people’s intuitions (Greene et al. 2001 ; Nichols 2002 ), and the hypothesis that concrete cases involving wrongdoing are likely to elicit blame-involving emotions (Nichols and Knobe 2007 ). But this is only a tentative suggestion.

The blame validation hypothesis is not the hypothesis that people are sometimes subject to the process of blame validation in some experimental study or other. Rather, it’s the hypothesis that participants in the experimental studies under consideration are subject to the process of blame validation.

Since the mean rating for can (M = −33.01) is lower than the mean rating for blame (M = −15.48), and since 29 participants provided ratings for can that are above the midpoint, we have some reason to think that more than 29 participants provided ratings for blame that are above the midpoint.

Henne et al. ( 2016 : 288) say that most people’s retraction of the claim that Brit ought to meet Dan suggests that ‘ought’ implies 'blame', and that this principle accords with Chituc et al.’s results. It is likely that they meant the converse since Chituc et al.’s results seem to support the converse principle,  and since it is possible for someone to be obligated to do something without being blameworthy for anything.

Alicke, M. (2000). Culpable control and the psychology of blame. Psychological Bulletin, 126 (4), 556–574.

Article   Google Scholar  

Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2015). Inability and obligation in moral judgment. PloS One, 10 (8), 1–20.

Chituc, V., Henne, P., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & De Brigard, F. (2016). Blame, not ability, impacts moral “ought” judgments for impossible actions: Toward an empirical refutation of “ought” implies “can”. Cognition, 150 , 20–25.

Graham, P. A. (2011). ‘Ought’ and ability. Philosophical Review, 120 (3), 337–382.

Greene, J., Sommerville, R., Nystrom, L., Darley, J., & Cohen, J. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293 (5537), 2105–2108.

Hannon, M. (forthcoming). Intuitions, reflective judgments, and experimental philosophy. Synthese . doi: 10.1007/s11229-017-1412-1 .

Henne, P., Chituc, V., De Brigard, F., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2016). An empirical refutation of “ought” implies “can”. Analysis, 76 (3), 283–290.

Kurthy, M., & Lawford-Smith, H. (2015). A brief note on the ambiguity of ‘ought’. Reply to Moti Mizrahi’s ‘ought, can and presupposition: An experimental study’. Methode, 4 (6), 244–249.

Google Scholar  

Kurthy, M., Lawford-Smith, H., & Sousa, P. (2017). Does ought imply can? PloS One, 12 (4), 1–24.

Mizrahi, M. (2015a). Ought, can, and presupposition: An experimental study. Methode, 4 (6), 232–243.

Mizrahi, M. (2015b). Ought, can, and presupposition: A reply to Kurthy and Lawford-smith. Methode, 4 (6), 250–256.

Nichols, S. (2002). Norms with feeling. Cognition, 84 (2), 221–236.

Nichols, S., & Knobe, J. (2007). Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive science of folk intuitions. Noûs, 41 (4), 663–685.

Schroer, J., & Schroer, R. (2013). Two potential problems with philosophical intuitions: Muddled intuitions and biased intuitions. Philosophia, 41 (4), 1263–1281.

Vranas, P. (2007). I ought, therefore I can. Philosophical Studies, 136 (b), 167–216.

Zimmerman, M. (1996). The concept of moral obligation . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Philosophy Department, University of Southern Maine, 122 Payson Smith Hall, Portland, ME, 04102, USA

Yishai Cohen

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yishai Cohen .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cohen, Y. An Analysis of Recent Empirical Data on ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’. Philosophia 46 , 57–67 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9892-2

Download citation

Received : 07 September 2016

Revised : 25 July 2017

Accepted : 27 July 2017

Published : 08 August 2017

Issue Date : March 2018

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-017-9892-2

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Blame validation
  • Experimental philosophy
  • Ought implies can
  • Find a journal
  • Publish with us
  • Track your research

IMAGES

  1. Recent experimental work on “ought” implies “can”

    experimental philosophy ought implies can

  2. PPT

    experimental philosophy ought implies can

  3. (PDF) PHIL 417

    experimental philosophy ought implies can

  4. PPT

    experimental philosophy ought implies can

  5. Video Abstract: Recent Experimental Work on "Ought" Implies "Can"

    experimental philosophy ought implies can

  6. ‘Ought-lmplies-Can’ and Hume's Rule

    experimental philosophy ought implies can

VIDEO

  1. Lesson 13.5. Ought Implies Can

  2. Experimental Philosophy (Podcast)

  3. The Integration of Philosophy and Psychology: Exploring Experimental Philosophy

  4. The Quiet Mind

  5. What is OUGHT IMPLIES CAN? What does OUGHT IMPLIES CAN mean? OUGHT IMPLIES CAN meaning & explanatio

  6. Most SIGNIFICANT lesson from STOICISM